美文网首页
Review and Criticism Philosophic

Review and Criticism Philosophic

作者: 传播学邓建国 | 来源:发表于2020-08-24 11:13 被阅读0次

    Review and Criticism Philosophical Approaches to Communication Theory

    A review essay by John Lyne, University of Pittsburgh

    Signs Grow: Semiosis and Life Processes. By Floyd Merrell. Toronto, Canada:

    UniversityofTorontoPress,1996.xii+341pp.$24.95(soft),$65.00(hard).

    Of Problematology: Philosophy, Science, and Language. By Michel Meyer. Trans.

    by David Jamison in collaboration with Alan Hart. Chicago: University of Chicago

    Press,1995.vii+310pp.$18.95(soft),$49.95(hard).

    Beyond the Symbol Model: Reflections on the Representational Nature of Language.

    Edited by John Stewart. Albany: SUNY Press, 1996. vi + 343 pp. $21.95 (soft),

    $65.50(hard).

    Language as Articulate Contact: Toward a Post-Semiotic Philosophy of Communication. By John Stewart. Albany: SUNY Press, 1995. vix + 303 pp. $19.95 (soft).

    Irecalltakingaclasslongagoinwhichwewereaskedtolearnalistofdifferent

    theories of how communication began. The theories were given catchy names for

    mnemonic purposes. There was the “bow-wow” theory, for instance, which was

    the position that communication originated in mimicking sounds in the environment. The “yo-he-ho” theory, by contrast, posited that the need to coordinate

    work required a rhythmic sounding out. So on down the list, we picked up each

    oftheconspicuoususesofcommunication.Onlyyearslaterdiditoccurtomethat

    thesestoriesoforiginwerenotreallypointsofanthropologicaldisputebutcompeting ways of thinking about language and communication. Arguments from

    originsareoftenthinlydisguisedexhortationstoembraceawayofthinking.

    Giving historical primacy to what one regards as the most essential aspect of

    communication is a common enough rhetorical strategy—in the origin stories

    logical priority is buttressed by temporal priority. One might have expected the

    retreat of philosophical foundationalism to eliminate the need to found and anchor communication in such ways. In fact, it seems only to have produced a shift

    intherhetoricalstrategies.Thefamiliarimpulseremains,maybebecauseitisone

    and the same as the philosophical impulse. The philosophical approaches reviewed here are engaged in a debate over rubrics, natures, and groundings. These

    are not, nor do they attempt to be, balanced accounts, giving a nod in each

    theoreticaldirection.Theyareinsteadfightingforthesoulofcommunication.

    Copyright © 1998 International Communication Association

    154

    Journal of Communication, Summer 1998

    JohnStewart’sLanguageasArticulateContactprovidesaclearanalysisofquite

    a number of major figures in the history and philosophy of language. He is also

    clear about his agenda to move communication theorists away from a representationalist paradigm (“the symbol model”), and so he makes an insistent case for an

    alternative,which,asperthetitle,is“articulatecontact.”Inspiredbythetradition

    of Heidegger and Gadamer, this model is hermeneutical rather than epistemological, and it has affinities with the dialogical approach of Mikhail Bahktin. In an

    unusualturn,Stewartalsolookstoissuesineducationofthedeaftoaddscopeto

    thenotionofarticulateness.

    A collection of essays edited by Stewart, Beyond the Symbol Model, was published as a companion volume, in which writers from several disciplines were

    invitedtodiscussthestatusoftherepresentationalmodeloflanguage.Mostembrace some version of the “postsemiotic” view, although one set of essays is

    groupedtogetherasresuscitationefforts,whichistosay,asattemptstocritique

    and preserve the symbolic function within the shifted framework. Unfortunately,

    spacedoesnotpermitdiscussingeachessayinthisusefulcollection.Aparticularly imaginative one by Andrew Smith presents a fictional dialogue between a

    followerofC.S.PeirceandaLyotardian.JohnShotternicelypresentshisdialogical Wittgenstinianism and argues for practical-moral knowledge as knowing of a

    third kind. Figures who loom large in this volume are Gadamer, Merleau-Ponty,

    Neitzsche,andothersofthecountertradition—onerapidlylosingitsmarginalized

    status.

    Thebasicproblemtobesurmounted,asStewartseesit(ArticulateContact),is

    a two worlds conception, with symbol and symbolized, signifier and signified,

    occupyingdifferentworlds.Itis,ashereadsit,alignedwithseveralotherfeatures

    ofthetraditionalstory,includingconceptionsoflanguageasasystemgoverning

    atomisticunitsandconstructingrepresentation.Thealternativeistotakelanguage

    asconstitutive,notinthelimitedsenseofthe“rules”theorists,butinsomething

    like the Heideggerian sense of the dwelling place of being. Such being, in this

    case, is emphatically interactive and a matter of contact among human beings in

    whatare,optimally,dialogicaleventsofarticulation.

    For Stewart it seems that the contest between these two conceptions is a zero

    sumgame:Ifoneallowsanysemiotic,referential,orrepresentationalfunctionto

    language,oneisonacollisioncoursewithlanguageasarticulatecontact.Agood

    deal of his book is about the history of the semiotic seduction, which can be

    found even among those theorists who think they have resisted it. Semioticians

    who pride themselves on moving beyond simple correspondence models, for

    instance,retaintwocentralerrorsofthetradition:representationandsystematicity.

    Whatever the success semiotics has had in recasting familiar objects as complex

    signconstructions,Stewartbelievesitiscarryingthewaterfortheoldtwoworlds

    theory.

    The pragmatic reader might hope for some accommodation of the two opposing models. Granting that language originates in the attempt to make articulate

    contactwithanother(callitthe“hithere”theory),whatprecludesmutuallycoordinatedactsofreferenceandrepresentation?Thisquestionisineffectaddressed

    by several essays in the edited collection. Stewart’s answer is that one cannot

    155

    Review and Criticism

    plausiblyandcoherentlysubscribetoapositionthatadmitsbothpossibilities.He

    argues that language cannot be both constitutive and instrumental, even though

    thatis,forexample,exactlythepositionofthespeechacttheorists,whodonot

    seemlogicallydefenseless.

    Stewart’sdefininggesturedoesnotcallattentiontoitself:rejectingthevocabularyofcorrespondencesandembracingthatofcoherences.Attimesthisispersuasive,butitisdonesounsparinglythatonemightexpectthatthebanishedcorrespondence function will reenter under a different guise, such as adequacy of

    “description,”forinstance.Stewartseemstobepushingthestrongcasepartlyfor

    itsrhetoricalimpact—theallieshequotesactuallysaythatlanguageisnotsimply

    a tool (Gadamer) or just a system of signs, etc. The two worlds terminology,

    however, is uncomfortably grafted onto some of the theories in question. For

    instance,Ithinkmostfanstosemioticswouldsaytheall-pervasivedistinctions

    between word and world, sign and signified, name and object, far from sorting

    out two worlds, are understood semiotically as internal to language, part of how

    itgetstractionininferencemaking.

    In the preface Stewart notes that some have questioned why the alternatives

    must be mutually exclusive—why he could not position himself as arguing for a

    theory of communication that is complementary to the semiotic one. I must confessthatthequestionneverleftthisreader’smind.Timeandagaininreviewinga

    hostofdifferenttheorists,Stewartappliesthelitmustest.Few,itseems,areuncontaminated by representational views, although Volosinov, Kenneth Burke, and

    CalvinSchragfarereasonablywell.Thetensionbetweensemioticandpostsemiotic

    elements in fact proves a useful device here for interrogating these and other

    writers. Why spoil it by knocking out one side of the interplay?

    Wittgensteinsaidthelimitsofone’slanguagewerethelimitsofone’sworld.In

    Signs Grow, Floyd Merrell has in a sense reversed this, making signifying a manifestationofanaturalorder.Inhislatestbookonsemiotics,Merrelldefiesmerely

    conventionalist explanations of language. He wants an account that gives it a

    naturallife,andinawaythatmightbetenableattheturnofthecurrentcentury,

    when we can no longer appeal to the élan vital. The comparison of sign making

    to DNA is more analogy than metaphor here—Merrell treats signs as “process

    structures”andsemiosisasaliving,growingnaturalprocess.Thereisnonature–

    culturedichotomytobefoundinthisanalysis.Maybethiswillcatchtheattention

    of those who have recently been arguing for a biologically based theory of communication, but I suspect they would make odd company. His frame of reference

    is populated by some unexpected allies, but especially by Peirce, and by the work

    ofphysicistIlyaPrigogine.Merrelltakesusthroughaspiralofcosmology,physics, semiotics, and psychology, pursuing the theme of self-organization and tapping Eastern as well as Western tropes. The book has an expansive spirit of

    “ecstaticnaturalism,”atermonceappliedtoPeirce.

    Merrell and Stewart could hardly be more different in their interpretation of

    Peirce.WhereasStewartunderstandshimasimplicatedinalonghistoricalprejudice toward representationalism, Merrell takes Peirce as a beacon to the future,

    anticipating the best aspects of postmodern understanding. Such divergent readings of Peirce are not new. Like most seminal figures, his work becomes a kind of

    156

    Journal of Communication, Summer 1998

    Rorschachtest,allowingaffiliationforverydifferent,sometimescontradictory,

    reasons.ThecoreofMerrell’sworkisaninvestigationofPeirce’ssemiotics,emphasizingthegrowing,changing,asymmetricalprocessesofsignification.Merrell

    is a determined symmetry-buster, well armed for that task. He pushes free of the

    static conception of language as a system, represented in the widely used terminologyofrulesandgames;hefaultsSaussurianstructuralismforthesamereason.

    With Prigogine, he argues that nonequilibrium is the key to growth and selforganizationinopensystems.Aswiththeuniverse,sowithsemiosis.Livingprocess is not simply transformation—it is growth. Merrell pursues imagery of an

    unfolding (and folding back) across a formidable, occasionally eccentric, landscape of process theories and cosmologies (call it the “grow and go” theory).

    Peirce serves equally well here as a theorist of signs and an anti-Cartesian

    theorist of consciousness, coming into his own as an intellectual force with the

    falteringofmodernism.Merrell’sPeirce-Prigoginealliance,whichseemsalready

    justifiedinPrigogine’swork,isquiteforward-looking.ThisPeirceshowsnothing

    of the two worlds view. Merrell quotes him saying that “every sign stands for an

    objectindependentofitself;butitcanonlybeasignofthatobjectinsofarasthat

    objectisitselfofthenatureofasignorthought”(p.63).Thepictureisofaworld

    perfused with signs, in which our participation is dynamic and transformative.

    Merrell would concur with Stewart on the point that language cannot be reduced

    toasystem.

    Michel Meyer is a professor of philosophy and rhetoric at the University of

    Brussels.Hisproject,inOfProblematology,beginswiththetropeofthe“crisis”in

    Western philosophy occasioned by the dissolution of a Cartesian subject in academic culture. It is as if the ground had been pulled from under us, and we lack

    an anchor point. Rather than abandoning philosophy, though, Meyer holds that

    we must again find a guiding principle, and that principle turns out to be the

    principleofquestioning,especiallyself-questioning.Givingupfoundationalism

    tolookforgroundinginbedrockprinciplemaysoundabitlikefryingpantofire

    forsomereaders;IbelieveMeyer’sresponseisthatquestioningistheonlygrounding

    thatperpetuallyproblematizesitself.ThisisclosetoSocrates’soracularinsight

    that he was wise because he knew that he did not know. Socrates plays out as a

    kind of hero in this, but a tragic one, whose death was inevitable. We have been

    on the wrong road ever since—this is, among other things, the story of fateful

    turning points. Modernist philosophy—and this traces to the Greeks—follows the

    modelofpropositionaljustification.Itlaborsundertheillusionthatitcansecure

    answers, putting the questions behind. By contrast, the philosophy of the unsettlingquestionistobecalled“problematology.”

    There is a real tension in Meyer’s book between his postfoundationist outlook

    and his quest for reliable origins. He wants a secure starting point, even while

    problematology would keep the ground undulating. Much seems to hinge on the

    radicalityofallthis(p.238),asthoughanythinglesswouldbecollusionwiththe

    justificationist model. The tone of radicality is so strong here that one hardly

    knows where to turn to find good models of such questioning (call it the “whywhy” theory). Science and the human sciences have pointed only toward objectificationandarethereforeofnohelp.Dialectic,somereaderswillbedisappointed

    157

    Review and Criticism

    to learn, is the bewitching enemy of problematology. The “dialecticization of

    interrogation,”Meyersays,wasthefirststeptowarditsrepressionasontology(p.

    124).Weneedtogetintothehabitoftreatinganswers,notassettlements,butas

    openings to new questions. In one chapter Meyer turns to the notion of interactive argumentation as a model, and he illustrates his point by showing a number

    of assertions that actually might be understood as opening new questions, expandingratherthanconcludingtheinquiry.Unfortunately,theseareratherpedestrianexamples,notmuchofapayoffforhavingembracedthespiritofradicalselfreflection.Thereisalsosomecommentaryonliteraryrhetoric.

    “Problematology”isnotaninherentlybeautifulterm(andperhapssix-syllable

    words do not make ready rallying cries), but Meyer is hoping to provide a worthy

    antithesistopropositionality.Itisworthnotingthatthelatterdoctrinebecame

    deeply rooted without actual use of that term. So maybe we should be thinking

    aboutstylesofanalysisratherthandefendingthesovereigntyofarubric.Kenneth

    Burke’s famous examination of metaphysical systems as the patient working out

    oftheimplicationsofasingletermsuggestshowfaronecangetwithasteadfast

    commitment to one dominant perspective. This is still much about naming. For

    Burke, however, the lesson is that all perspectives are just that: perspectives,

    responsibly judged by proportionality rather than purity. Viewed as a rhetorical

    genre, questioning is one among many, and at some point “questioning” must

    itselfbequestioned,lestweloseoutonconstitutinganddeclaringordisagreeing

    andcontrolling.

    Thegestureof“radicalreflection”canbecleansinguptoapoint.Thereisso

    much radical reflection in this volume, though, that one begins to wonder how

    thisoranyotherphilosophycouldpossiblythinkofitselfassoradicallyaccessible to itself—how it could find a shortcut to reality without making a detour

    throughthechanginglandscapeofscience,media,andpolitics.Itisatleastinvigorating to see someone like Merrell thinking about the nature of communication within a wide range of human knowledge and practices. How could the

    advent of quantum physics not be important to a present-day metaphysics? Or the

    discovery of DNA? The internet? If those earth-shaking changes become only

    incidental to our philosophies, then it seems to me we will have left ourselves

    insufficientspaceforthetheoryofcommunication.Ourchallengeistostayopen

    tothebeingsandrealitiesthatenterandexitourworld,andnotjusttothosethat

    areontologicallygrandfatheredin.

    The comingling of different forms of knowledge and different ontologies poses

    some of our most interesting questions. If language gives us the power to articulate,toquestion,tounderstand,ortosignify,italsohaswaysofthwartingthose

    things—or, for better or worse, of making us think we are achieving communion

    when we are really only confused. It would be nice to see basic thinking on

    communication more frequently take into its purview the problem of symbolic

    confusion, otherwise known to Cool Hand Luke fans as failure to communicate.

    This is perhaps the justification we would provide for our own work and livelihoods, should we be called before the legislature (call it the “keep working”

    theory). Were the writers discussed here convened in a room, I doubt they would

    becontenttotalkpasteachother.

    相关文章

      网友评论

          本文标题:Review and Criticism Philosophic

          本文链接:https://www.haomeiwen.com/subject/hczgjktx.html