1.2.c&m

作者: 不自同雏机 | 来源:发表于2018-05-23 17:41 被阅读0次

    41

    With the Critique, the “tribunal of pure reason” had passed a sentence on theoretical metaphysics that was universally valid and promised a lasting peace  between  the  parties  to  the  dispute:  The  pretensions  of  dogmatic  reason have been dismissed once and for all since it has been shown that there cannot in principle be any theoretical cognition outside of possible experience. The fundamental objections of skeptical reason are also overruled, since it has been shown that, in relation to possible experience, a priori cognition is indeed real and demonstrable: “Reason, when employed apart from all experience, can know propositions entirely a priori, and as necessary, or it can know nothing at all. Its judgments, therefore, are never opinions; either it must abstain from all judgment, or must affirm with apodictic certainty” (A775).

    However, if we go on to ask just what it is, according to this sentence, that can be known by theoretical reason with apodictic certainty, the answer is sobering to say the least:

    1)  All appearances are, in their intuition, extensive magnitudes (A162).

    2)  In all appearances, sensation and the real, which is its object, has intensive magnitude, that is, a degree (A166).

    3)  All appearances contain the permanent (substance) as the object itself and the transitory as its mere determination, that is, as a way in which the object exists (A182).

    4)  Everything that happens, that is, begins to be,presupposes something upon which it follows according to a rule (A189).

    5)  All substances, so far as they coexist, stand in thoroughgoing community, that is, in mutual interaction (A211).

    6)  That which agrees with the formal conditions of experience, that is, with the conditions of intuition and of concepts, is possible

     (A218).

    42

    7)  That which is bound up with the material conditions of experience, that is, with sensation, is

    actual(A218).

    8)  That which in its connection with the actual is determined inaccordance with universal conditions of experience, is (that is, exists as) necessary(A218).

    That is all that theoretical reason can know a priori. We cannot help but ask whether this answer is worth the effort that went into finding it. 

    As Kant puts it, “It is humiliating to human reason that it achieves nothing in its pure [i.e. theoretical] employment, and indeed stands in need of a discipline to check its extravagancies, and to guard it against the deceptions which arise therefrom . . .  The greatest and perhaps the sole use of all  philosophy  of  pure  reason  is  therefore  only  negative;  since  it  serves not as an organon for the extension but as a discipline for the limitation of  pure  reason,  and,  instead  of  discovering  truth,  has  only  the  modest  merit of guarding against error” (A795).

    For Kant, of course, there is more to the task of philosophy than just this, for besides its theoretical employment there is also a practical employment of reason: “Consequently, if there be any correct employment of pure reason, in which case there must also be a canon1 of its employment, the canon will deal not with the speculative but with the practical employment  of  reason.  This  practical  employment  of  reason  we  shall  now proceed to investigate” (A797). The ultimate signifi cance of the task of the Critique was that in restricting theoretical reason’s claims to knowledge, it secured to morality a fi eld exclusively its own: the Critique was to be followed not only by a metaphysics of nature, but also by a metaphysics of morals. For Kant was convinced that practical reason contains pure laws— the moral laws— which we can know a priori and which are not subject to a dialectic, thus allowing for a canon of the proper use of reason. The lesson of Rousseau, Kant believed, was that even the philosophically uneducated know what it is moral to do, so that the task of philosophy consists merely in explicating and bringing into view the underlying principle. In the Critique’s Doctrine of Method, in the chapter on ‘The Canon of Pure Reason’, Kant writes that he is justifi ed in assuming that there actually are such pure moral laws which command the will in a completely a priori manner, in that he can appeal “not only to the

    ——————————————————————————————————————————

    1

    “I  understand  by  a  canon  the  sum-  total  of  the  a  priori  principles  of  the  c

    43

    proofs  employed  by  the  most  enlightened  moralists,  but  to  the  moral  judgment of every man, in so far as he makes the effort to think such a law clearly” (A807). Note, however, that Kant is not concerned  here with the question, ‘Whatought I to do?’, which as such is a purely practical question and hence “not  transcendental  but  rather  moral,  and  cannot,  therefore,  in  and  by  itself, form a proper subject for treatment in this critique” (A805). The question that Kant treats is rather: ‘If I do what I ought to do, what may I  then  hope?’  As  he  emphasizes,  this  question  is  at  once  both  practical  and theoretical and therefore still part of the present subject. For it can serve to explain why reason, in spite of the dialectic and the theoretical agnosticism to which it leads, time and again ventures beyond the limits of experience and is compelled to confront three problems constituting he ultimate purpose of reason: the freedom of the will, the immortality of the soul, and the existence of God. The practical question, What ought I to do?, provides merely the “guiding thread” for answering the theoretical question. What is meant by this?

    Since the answer to the fi rst, practical, question is: ‘Do that through which thou becomest worthy of being happy’, the second question comes

    to mean: ‘If I behave as I must in order to be worthy of happiness, may I

    hope 

    thereby

    to obtain happiness?’ In other words, Kant is asking whether

    the principles of pure reason, which prescribe the moral law a priori, also

    necessarily connect the hope of happiness with it. And, he claims, indeed

    it can: “I maintain that just as the moral principles are necessary accord-

    ing to reason in its

    practical

    employment, it is in the view of reason, in

    the fi eld of its

    theoretical

    employment, no less necessary to assume that

    everyone has ground to hope for happiness in the mea sure in which he

    has rendered himself by his conduct worthy of it, and that the system of

    morality is therefore inseparably— though only in the idea of pure reason— 

    bound  up  with  that  happiness”  (A809).  How  does  Kant  arrive  at  this  

    conclusion?

    We can imagine a possible world in which all human action takes place

    in accord with the moral laws. In such a moral world, whose idea abstracts

    from all obstacles to morality, we ourselves would be the authors of both

    our own happiness and that of others, for the moral law prescribes that

    we further “what is best in the world, alike in ourselves and in others” 

    (A819), i.e. each must make the happiness of others his duty. In such a

    world, the proportionality of virtue and happiness must therefore be

    “con-

    ceived as necessary” (A809). Moral happiness is the result of a reciprocal

    44

    exercise of virtue and is thus largely in

    dependent of nature.2 In addition to such moral happiness, Kant also acknowledges physical happiness, 

    which is dependent on nature and consists in the maximal satisfaction of

    our sensuous desires (cp. A800, 806). Since my various desires are often

    in confl ict with each other, so that the fulfillment

    of one precludes the fulfillment of another, the task of reason is to

    establish an order that allows  for  the  greatest  possible 

    satisfaction  overall.  As  a  sensuous  being  with needs and desires, I

    inevitably pursue such happiness, but it is ulti-

    mately  empirically  contingent  and,  without  morality,  it  is  not  actually  

    true happiness.3

    True happiness, which would reign in a moral world in exact

    proportion  to  virtue,  thus  presupposes  that  everyone does  what 

    he  ought” (A810). In our actual world that is not, of course, the case.

    Hence the

    moral happiness of individuals is

    defactounachievable; physical happiness, on the other hand, is

    subject to empirical contingencies and stands in  a  merely  contingent 

    relation  to  one’s  own  morality.  Additionally,  in our world we

    cannot abstract from the obstacles to morality. Not infrequently, moral

    demands starkly confl ict with one’s own desires, so that moral action

    entails physical disadvantages for oneself. Nevertheless, the

    obligatory force of this categorical ‘thou shalt’ remains unaffected by all

    such concerns. Reason therefore fi nds itself compelled to assume a differ-

    ent connection between morality and happiness. For it is after all one and

    the same reason which both posits the moral law and is responsible for

    the  equally  paramount  task—  called  “prudence”  (A800,  806)— 

    of  promoting my empirical happiness.  Were the two fundamental demands

    of morality and prudence irreconcilable, reason would either despair or,

    at

    the very least, be deterred from morality. Under such circumstances being

    moral would be extremely imprudent, for it would be in no way to my

    advantage. Though the moral law would allow us to conceive the idea of

    ______________________________________________________________________

    2

      “.  .  .  inasmuch  as  freedom,  partly  inspired  and  partly  restricted  by  moral  laws,  

    would  itself  be  the  cause  of  general  happiness,  since  rational  beings,  under  the  

    guidance  of  such  principles,  would  themselves  be  the  authors  both  of  their  own  

    enduring well- being and of that of others” (A809).

    3

    In refl ection 6907, written during the period in which Kant was at work on the

    Critique,

    we read: “Happiness is twofold: either that which is an effect of the free

    choice (Willkühr) of rational beings in themselves, or that which is only a contin-

    gent and external effect dependent on nature. By way of actions which are mutually

    directed toward each other, rational beings can create True Happiness (

    die Wahre Glükseeligkeit) which is in dependent of everything in nature and without it nature

    cannot produce happiness in the proper sense” (19:202).

    45

    a perfect action, it could never provide any motivation to act. But such a

    state of affairs is irreconcilable with the categorical obligatory force of the

    law: “Since there are practical laws which are absolutely necessary, that is, 

    the moral laws, it must follow that if these necessarily presuppose the ex-

    istence of any being as the condition of the possibility of their

    obligatory 

    power,

    this existence must be

    postulated

    ” (A633– 34, cp. 815). In order

    for the moral law actually to motivate actions, a proportion between vir-

    tue and happiness must at least be

    possible,

    even if experience does not

    appear to offer suffi cient evidence of such a proportion. For Kant, however, 

    the possibility of such a proportion is only given on the assumption of a

    just God and a life after death.

    Morality,  by  itself,  constitutes  a  system.  Happiness,  however,  

    does not do so, save in so far as it is distributed in exact propor-

    tion to morality. But this is possible only in the intelligible world, 

    under a wise Author and Ruler. Such a Ruler, together with life in

    such  a  world,  which  we  must  regard  as  a  future  world,  reason  

    fi nds itself constrained to assume; otherwise it would have to re-

    gard the moral laws as empty fi

    gments of the brain, since without

    this postulate the necessary consequence which it itself connects

    with  these  laws  could  not  follow.  .  .  .    It  is  

    necessary

      that  the  

    whole  course  of  our  life  be  subject  to  moral  maxims;  but  it  is  

    impossible

    that this should happen unless reason connects with

    the  moral  law,  which  is  a  mere  idea,  an  operative  cause  which  

    determines for such conduct as is in accordance with the moral

    law an outcome, either in this or in another life, that is in exact

    conformity  with  our  supreme  ends.  Thus  without  a  God  and  

    without a world invisible to us now but hoped for, the glorious

    ideas of morality are indeed objects of approval and admiration, 

    but not springs of purpose and action.

    For they do not fulfi

    ll in

    its completeness that end which is natural to every rational being

    and  which  is  determined  a  priori  

    by  that  same

      pure  reason  

    (A811– 13, emphasis added).

    Thus the theoretical and practical interests of reason are at last united in

    the idea of the highest good of a future world in which virtue and happi-

    ness correspond. We must be able to conceive of ourselves as belonging

    to such a world if reason is to accord with itself. “Thus God and a future

    life are two postulates which, according to the principles of pure reason, 

    are  inseparable  from  the  obligation  which  that  same  reason  imposes  

    upon us” (A811)

    46

    With this I can conclude my present discussion of the

    Critique of Pure

    Reason.

    There is just one last point to which I would like to call atten-

    tion. If the discovery of the main transcendental question and the prob-

    lem of the antinomy had shown that prior to the Critique there could not

    have been any scientifi c philosophy based in pure reason, after the com-

    pletion  of  this  work  Kant  can  now  hold  out  the  prospect  of  perfecting  

    such a science “in a short time” (Axx), indeed “before the end of the pres-

    ent century” (A856). Since this science is “nothing but the

    inventory of all our possession through pure reason, systematically arranged,” all that

    is required for its perfection is the enumeration of all the derivative con-

    cepts (for which Kant desires the “assistance of a fellow worker” [Axxi], 

    as  well  as  the  systematic  exposition  of  all  possible  cognition  through  

    pure concepts: “Such a system of pure (speculative) reason I hope myself

    to produce under the title Metaphysics of Nature.It will be not half as

    large, yet incomparably richer in content than this present critique, which

    has as its fi rst task to discover the sources and conditions of the possibil-

    ity of such a metaphysics” (Axxi).

    Before Kant could begin working out the system in detail, however, he

    had  planned  a  short  book  intended  to  facilitate  understanding  of  the  

    Critique.

    As mentioned above, Kant was aware of the extraordinary dif-

    fi culties that such a completely new “mode of thought” and the compre-

    hension  of  the  underlying  “plan”  was  bound  to  cause  the  unprepared  

    reader. The Critique had only just left the press when he communicated

    to Marcus Herz that he knew he could not at fi rst expect many readers

    who  would  carefully  study  his  book,  but  that  he  was  contemplating  a  

    plan for rendering the work more popular. That was not possible at the

    outset,  “because  the    whole  system  of  this  sort  of  knowledge  had  to  be  

    exhibited in all its articulation” (10:269), but it could happen now that

    that  had  been  accomplished.  He  presented  this  simpler  plan  two  years  

    later  in  the  form  of  the  Prolegomena  to  Any  Future  Metaphysics  That  

    Will be Able to Come Forward as Science

     (1783).

    Whereas  the  Critique was  forced  to  take  the  more  diffi  cult  path  of  

    investigating reason itself and, “without relying on any fact what ever,” to

    derive cognition from its original sources, the Prolegomena were to be a

    kind of preparatory exercise: “they ought more to indicate what needs to

    be done in order to bring a science into existence if possible than to pres-

    ent  the  science  itself.  They  must  therefore  rely  on  something  already  

    known  to  be  dependable”  (4:274–  75).  So,  in  contrast  to 

    the  Critique,they take an acknowledged “fact” as the starting point.

    47

    It is mathematics and pure natural science in which Kant fi

    nds such a

    starting point. For he sees both sciences as containing synthetic knowl-

    edge which is at once both apodictically certain and in

    de pendent of experience, and thus a priori. Since the propositions of metaphysics (assum-

    ing its possibility) are also synthetic and a priori, it seems natural to ask

    whether  the  conditions  of  possibility  of  synthetic  a  priori  judgments  in  

    mathematics and pure natural science are not also the conditions under

    which such judgments would be possible in metaphysics. “We have therefore some at least

    uncontested synthetic cognition a priori, and we do not

    need to ask whether it is possible (for it is actual), but only:  how is it possible,

    in order to be able to derive, from the principle of the possibility

    of the given cognition, the possibility of all other synthetic

    cognition a priori” 

    (4:275). Hence “the main transcendental question” on which the plan of

    the Prolegomena is based is not ‘How can a priori representations

    veridically refer to objects in general?’, as in the Critique, but

    rather: ‘How are synthetic judgments a priori possible?’ (cp. 4:280,

    276).

    The method of the Prolegomenahas both advantages and disadvantages.

    The main advantage is that since the text begins with somethingfamiliar

    to the reader which is then analyzed step by step, the steps of

    theargument are easier to follow. The  whole is thus capable of a

    certain popularity which the more strictly academic exposition of the

    Critique could not have hoped for. It is also far easier to recognize 

    here than in the Critique what is crucial for the possibility of

    synthetic judgments a priori: 

    namely the ideality of space and time. As Kant emphasizes, it is “the sole

    means for solving this problem” (4:377). The fundamental disadvantage

    is that the regressive- analytic method leads to a result which is valid only

    conditionally, valid, that is, only to the extent that the premise (the “fact”) 

    is correct. For though Kant is certain for his part that the propositions of

    mathematics and pure natural science are synthetic a priori, it is certainly

    possible to doubt that they are as Hume, for example, had done. The

    Prolegomena,therefore, can only supplement the Critique or follow upon it, 

    not replace it. The method of the Prolegomena is useful against

    dogmatism because it makes clear the limits of possible knowledge from

    pure

    reason. It is less successful against skepticism, however, because it presup-

    poses that there really are synthetic judgments a priori, instead of deriving

    them from the possibility of thought (apperception) as in the subjective

    deduction of the categories. And of course this method also excludes mo-

    rality  from  transcendental  philosophy;  its  possibility  cannot  be  derived  

    from that of pure mathematics and natural science.

    48

    Just as Kant was busy with the composition of the

    Prolegomena, the first review of the Critique

    was published in the Göttingische Anzeigen

    von gelehrten Sachen.

    The importance of this review for the further development  of  Kant’s  philosophy  cannot  be  overestimated  and  hence  I  

    will deal with it  here in somewhat greater detail

    48

    Just as Kant was busy with the composition of the Prolegomena,the first review of the Critique was published in the Göttingische Anzeigen von gelehrten Sachen.

    The importance of this review for the further development  of  Kant’s  philosophy  cannot  be  overestimated  and  hence  I will deal with it  here in somewhat greater detail.

    相关文章

      网友评论

          本文标题:1.2.c&m

          本文链接:https://www.haomeiwen.com/subject/ebxdjftx.html